Resources --> Library --> Response to "The Internet and the Future..."
Response to "The Internet and the Future of Democratic Governance"
By Senator Mike Gravel, November 18, 2000
Responding to an article by Sen. Patrick J. Leahy and Rep. Robert Goodlatte.
The authors of this
Briefing correctly identify the areas affected by the Internet's
impact on governance, but their assessment of the extent of that
impact is far too modest. I share the level of optimism found in
many of the other Briefings: that the Internet portends fundamental
changes on the order of those resulting from the Gutenberg Press
that ushered in the Ages of Discovery and Enlightenment, thence
to individual sovereignty setting the stage for constitutional democracy.
The Internet, in my view, will usher in the Age of Democracy, the
essence of which will be republican governance -- the majoritarian
expression of the popular sovereignty of people,1 an
age where citizens "shall make and shall obey their own laws, shall
be at once their own subjects and their own masters"2
Enhancing The Status
Quo
This Briefing is decidedly
government-centered. "The Internet's potential to enhance democratic
governance" by promoting "popular involvement" is immediately cautioned
that the enhancement should occur only "without diluting the advantages
of the republican form of government."3 This is "code" for: do not
dilute the power of representatives. It is difficult to see how
improving "popular involvement" within a polity of laws can negatively
dilute democratic governance.
Access to Government
Documents: The Briefing's assessment of what the Internet offers
for the delivery of government information is well made. Much greater
benefits however lie in moving the processing of the interface between
citizens and government onto the Internet. My recent online driver's
license renewal with the Virginia DMV was unexpectedly convenient
and efficient. With little attention or effort, filing of income
taxes online is on the rise. Clearly intra-governmental operations
are increasingly going online. It makes sense that the entire government-citizen
interface and interaction should begin to be vectored toward Internet
facilitation, digital divide aside, which will shortly be marginalized.
Online Voting and
Voter Turnout: The authors conclude on the strength of little
data that the convenience of Internet voting will increase voter
turnout. Knowledgeable political scientists,4 citing
other empirical data, do not believe convenience alone will increase
voting. If the latter are correct, then voter disenchantment goes
much deeper than matters of convenience. The turnout question is
misleading however. It is not the number of people who vote that
is important, but how well informed they are. To focus on body counts
at the polls tends to allow avoidance of the necessary, more important
examination of today's deeper problems of governance.
Americans have always
been suspicious of government controlled by politicians because
they know the representative structure is flawed. There is ample
evidence that for politicians their own self-interest and the economic
interests of their financial backers always come first. Half the
eligible citizens of our democracy choose not to participate as
voters. I believe a primary reason for their disenchantment involves
the structural limitation on the people's role in their own governance.
Far and away the Briefing's
most important instruction is the recommendation to fund "experiments
with Internet voting." This should be aggressively pursued, since
it is a vital first step toward capturing what the Internet has
to offer the people in their quest for total franchise.
Direct Democracy
This Briefing briefly
touches on the essence of human governance in noting the option
available with the Internet for government-by-plebiscite -- direct
democracy. On this question, which is fraught with historic and
constitutional misunderstandings, the Briefing is woefully unengaged.
Instead, the Briefing
voices the disputable opinion that "since the days of our Founding,
the idea of plebiscitory democracy has been viewed with considerable
suspicion." There is no question that elites of earlier generations
viewed the public's ability to govern with suspicion. They still
do. However, this is grossly inaccurate in that our nation was founded
on the ability of ordinary citizens to govern themselves as evidenced
by the Mayflower Compact, the New England Town Meeting, and the
continuation of orderly local governments after the Declaration
of Independence removed the elitist supervision of the Crown. The
overwhelming majority of Americans throughout our history never
suspected their ability to govern. Witness the overarching constitutional
efforts since 1789 that have resulted in the successful expansion
of the voting franchise and the empowerment of people.
The watershed expansion
of the franchise took place over a hundred years ago with the enactment
of initiative, referendum and recall laws by reformers in reaction
to the abject corruption of representatives in government. These
laws made lawmakers of a substantial number of Americans. The Internet
now suggests the same possibility for all Americans, addressing
the real reason for voter alienation.
Governance within the
American polity is structurally flawed. The Constitution limits
the power of government but gives unlimited control of that power
to a very small minority of individuals. Actually, the Framers had
no alternative but to define for us a representative legislative
structure. On June 6, 1787, at the Constitutional Convention, James
Wilson, second only to James Madison in fashioning the Constitution,
described the context of our republican structure:
The Legislature ought
to be the most exact transcript of the whole society. Representation
is made necessary only because it is impossible for the people
to act collectively.5
Wilson acknowledged the
obvious impossibility of assembling great numbers of people from
distant geographic areas to operate as a polity. Thus were technological
limitations in 1787 of crucial importance in determining the structure
of Congress as defined in the Constitution. Obviously the Internet,
if not today but certainly within a few years, will remove those
limitations, permitting the "virtual assembly" of people electronically,
locally and nationally.
Removing technological
barriers still leaves a constitutional question about the power
of the people to legislate in some minds. Two arguments put this
final objection to rest: historic instruction and contemporary practice.
First, Wilson's instructions are surprising to many who self-servingly
misread the Framers intent:
All power is originally
in the people and should be exercised by them in person, if that
could be done with convenience, or even with little difficulty.6
Second, today nineteen
states permit their citizens to legislate by initiative, California,
Missouri and Oregon for example. Additionally, twenty-three states
use referenda. A considerable number of local jurisdictions also
permit people to make laws. American citizens have a hand in making
laws in forty-two states. Even though these laws are different in
each state, the constitutional lawmaking powers of the people have
been repeatedly sustained by the Supreme Court.
Nevertheless, pundits,
government officials, scholars and assorted elites view initiative
lawmaking with suspicion because the initiative process, as they
see it, is not sufficiently deliberative. Deliberation is vital
to lawmaking. The charge is accurate. The original reformers writing
these laws, with little legislative experience, naively failed to
realize the need for detailed, deliberative, legislative procedures.
Moreover, since their enactment, initiative laws have been controlled
and administered by representative government officials increasingly
to the disadvantage of citizen lawmakers. Those officials, critics
of initiative laws, have had the power to make initiative laws deliberative,
but not only have they failed to do so, they made their use more
difficult, revealing their true attitude toward "service to the
people."
Not surprisingly, even
though the initiative laws lacked proper deliberation, the people's
legislative record for the last hundred years in states with initiative
laws is as good or better than the record of elected legislators;
a record detractors always fail to mention. Some of the nation's
foremost reforms were enacted by the people: women's right to vote,
old age assistance, the removal of civil service from party politics,
campaign finance reform and term limits, to name a few.
Yet, opponents still
continue to advance the groundless charges that the majority of
people, if given power, will oppress minorities and that they will
bankrupt their political jurisdictions by showering their treasuries
on themselves. Nowhere, in the last one hundred years, have these
charges been realized where people can legislate. Ironically, however,
the oppression of minorities and the bankrupting of political jurisdictions
has been characteristic of a number of representative governments.
The Direct Democracy
Initiative
In order to realize the
full potential of the Internet, the legislative powers of government
must be redistributed to permit the people to make laws in a parallel
partnership with their elected legislators, nationally and in every
local and state government jurisdiction of the United States. Deliberative
legislative procedures must to be enacted either as a constitutional
amendment or as a federal law in order to create a "Legislature
of the People."
The necessary legislative
procedures, similar to those of the Congress, are embodied in the
Direct Democracy Initiative (DDI), a proposed federal law sponsored
by Philadelphia Two.7 The law also creates an agency to administer
the legislative procedures -- the Electoral Trust.
It is unlikely that the
Congress or state legislatures will enact such legislation, in effect
diluting their power. Nevertheless, both proponents and opponents
of citizen lawmaking see the polity moving toward direct democracy.
The utility of the Internet is the driving force. Unless a thoughtful
legislative transition is made to include citizens in a lawmaking
role creating a partnership with their elected representatives,
the people will take control forcibly in a process that will of
necessity be disruptive, expensive and a threat to democracy itself.
A forcible process will impose laws at best similar to those that
presently exist in states -- laws that lack proper deliberative
procedures.
Rather than oppose advances
to higher democracy, political elites should encourage a smooth
transition for the people's involvement by endorsing the Direct
Democracy Initiative or something similar for submission to the
people in a manner suggested by James Madison at the Constitutional
Convention on three separate occasions:
The new Constitution should be ratified in the most exceptional
form, and by the supreme authority of the people themselves.8
These changes would make essential inroads on State Constitutions...and
in the case of these a ratification must of necessity be obtained
from the people.9
The people were in fact, the fountain of all power, and by resorting
to them, all difficulties were got over.10
Madison's call for ratification
by the people in a self-enacting process was the device the Framers
used to circumvent the certain opposition of Colonial State Legislatures
to the Constitution. The DDI employs a similar device to circumvent
the certain opposition of the Congress. Both the deliberative legislative
procedures similar to those of any legislature and the modern-day
self-enactment process proposed in the DDI can be examined in detail
online at: http://philadelphiatwo.org.
Conclusion
The complexities of human
governance have never been more challenging. The revolution in communications
technology is globalizing national economies and regional cultures
by democratizing individuals with the power of information and the
ability to act upon it individually. Present representative government
structures, more than two hundred years old, are mired in earlier
technologies and are ill equipped to stay abreast of the monumental
and rapid changes taking place in society.
Direct democracy suggests
a more mature participatory role for citizens than reliance only
on intermediaries in representative governments where representatives'
personal agendas and special interests always come first. More importantly,
citizens are denied, when forced to transfer their sovereign power
to others, the civic maturity that is gained from sharing the responsibilities
of government.
For the first time in
history, technology can permit great numbers of citizens from distant
places to assemble and participate directly in their self-governance
as lawmakers. If this opportunity is not taken, this same technology
could unleash scenarios for national and global anarchy by people
frustrated in their desire to exercise their sovereign role within
the polity. If we are not sufficiently mature to understand the
governing dysfunctions that presently occur and to anticipate those
that will occur by not fully sharing with the people the lawmaking
powers of the polity, then we condemn society to an uncertain and
dangerous future.
1Many constitutional
scholars erroneously interpret Article IV Section 4 of the Constitution,
the Republican Form of Government guarantee clause, to mean a guarantee
for representative government. They interpret the word republican
to mean representative. Our legislative structure is incidental
only to the technology of the day as noted by James Wilson. The
representative structure does not attach itself for all time to
the generic definitions of democracy or republic, two different
words with Latin and Greek roots with the same meanings -- public
and people. People rule in republics or democracies, employing whatever
structure or constitutional device recognizes majoritarian rule.
James Madison made this clear in the 3rd paragraph of Federalist
49: "As the people are the only legitimate fountain of power, and
it is from them that the constitutional charter, under which the
several branches of government hold their power, is derived, it
seems strictly consonant to the republican theory, to recur to the
same original authority, not only whenever it may be necessary to
enlarge, diminish, or new-model the powers of government, but whenever
any one of the departments may commit encroachments on the chartered
authorities of the others." Emphasis added.
2 Alexander
Meiklejohn, Political Freedom: The Constitutional Powers of the
People, Harper, New York, 1960, p 18. Meiklejohn was a renowned
constitutional scholar of the last century
3The
following sources enlarge the theory and meaning of the republican
guarantee clause of the Constitution:
Akhil Reed Amar, The
Central Meaning of Republican Government: Popular Sovereignty, Majority
Rule and the Denominator Problem, University of Colorado Law Review,
Vol. 65:4, 1994, p. 749. Max Farrand, ed, The Record of the Federal
Constitution of 1787, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1966, 92-93
(remarks by James Madison).
4 Frances Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward, Why Americans
Still Don't Vote: And Why Politicians Want It That Way, Beacon Press,
Boston, 2000, pp. 267-268.
5Max
Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Constitution of 1787, Yale
University Press, New Haven, 1966, Vol. I, pp. 132-133.
6 James
Wilson, The Works of James Wilson, ed. Robert Green McCloskey, The
Belnap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1967, Vol.
I, p. 405.
7 Philadelphia Two and Direct Democracy are nonprofit
corporations dedicated to the establishment of direct democracy
and are available for public inspection at http://philadelphiatwo.org.
8Jonathan Elliot's Debates, edited by James McClellan
and M.E. Bradford, Debates in the Federal Convention of 1787 as
reported by James Madison, Vol. III, James River Press, Richmond,
1989, p. 70. 9Ibid. p. 335.
10 Ibid. p. 534.
Back To Top